Books and Recent Papers of Eric Schechter

SET
THEORY
  Kelley's specialization of Tychonov's Theorem is equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem, Fundamenta Mathematicae 189 (2006), 285-288. In 1950 John L. Kelley published the first proof that Tychonov's Theorem (TT) implies the Axiom of Choice (AC). His proof was erroneous, but easily corrected; that was mentioned in 1951 by Los and Ryll-Nardzewski and presented in detail in 1972 by Plastria. The error involved this intermediate principle: (K) Any product of cofinite topologies is compact. The implication TT => K is trivial, but Kelley's proof of K => AC was faulty. The 1951 and 1972 papers replaced K with other, more complicated principles, thus leaving open this interesting question: is K => AC actually true by some other proof, or is it false? My paper shows that it's false. In fact, K turns out to be equivalent to BPI, which is well known to be strictly weaker than AC. 145kb pdf
 
REAL
ANALYSIS
  (with J. Alan Alewine) Topologizing the Denjoy Space by Measuring Equiintegrability. Real Analysis Exchange 31 (2005-06), 23-44. Basic limit theorems for the KH integral involve equiintegrable sets. We construct a family of Banach spaces whose bounded sets are precisely the subsets of KH[0,1] that are equiintegrable and pointwise bounded. Then KH[0,1] is the union of these Banach spaces, and can be topologized as their inductive limit. That topology is is barreled, bornological, and stronger than both pointwise convergence and the topology given by the Alexiewicz seminorm, but it lacks the countability and compatibility conditions that are often associated with inductive limits. 239kb pdf
 
LOGIC
  Classical and Nonclassical Logics. 507 + ix pages. Princeton University Press, August 2005. (This is not research, but rather a textbook -- i.e. it is not new discoveries, but my attempt to make more understandable some ideas that were already present in the research literature.) So-called classical logic is just one of the many kinds of reasoning present in everyday thought. When presented by itself -- as in most introductory texts on logic -- it seems arbitrary and unnatural to students new to the subject.  CNL introduces classical logic alongside constructive, relevant, comparative, and other nonclassical logics; the contrast illuminates all of them. Two of P.U.P.'s internal reviewers said
    It will be a valuable addition to the literature, especially as some of the topics covered have long been the preserve of specialists.

    The exposition is solid and successfully clarifies topics that traditionally are difficult to understand by a novice. ... The author shows that he has great ability to lucidly describe complicated ideas in various schools of logic.

Math Reviews (MR2164393) said
    Let us note that this is an introductory textbook for which no previous experience with mathematical logic is required. The author's style is clear and approachable, and, consequently, this book seems to be ideal for beginning students of both mathematics and philosophy, as well as for students of computer science and the large circle of logicians working in the field of nonclassical logics.
For further description see the book's web page, which includes a downloadable excerpt.
 
LOGIC
  Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox. Studia Logica 77 (2004), 117-128. Abstract: Relevant logic is a proper subset of classical logic. It does not include among its theorems any of positive paradox, mingle, linear order, or unrelated extremes. This article shows that those four formulas have different effects when added to relevant logic, and then lists many formulas that have the same effect as positive paradox or mingle. Preprint downloadable here (105 kb PDF file).
 
REAL
ANALYSIS
  (with J. Alan Alewine) Review of the recent book The Integral: An Easy Approach after Kurzweil and Henstock, by Peng Yee Lee and Rudolf Vyborny. Reviewed in the American Mathematical Monthly 108 (2001), 577-582. The review discusses this book and (to a lesser extent) some other, related books, with particular attention to where these books belong in our standard curriculum. You can read this paper online or download preprints available in several formats. For a slightly different introduction to the KH integral, see my web page on the subject.
 
PHILOSOPHY
OF MATH
  Constructivism is difficult. American Mathematical Monthly 108 (2001), 50-54. Abstract: Constructivism is unusually difficult to learn. Learning most mathematical subjects merely involves adding a little to one's knowledge, without disturbing what one already has, but learning constructivism involves modifying all aspects of what one already knows: theorems, methods of reasoning, technical vocabulary, and even the use of everyday words that do not seem technical, such as "or". In this paper I discuss, in the language of mainstream mathematicians, some of those modifications; perhaps newcomers to constructivism will not be so overwhelmed by it if they know what kinds of difficulties to expect. [Paper can be viewed online in html format. For better looking printed copies, please instead download the pdf version.]
 
DIFFERENTIAL
EQUATIONS
  (with Daniel Biles) Solvability of a finite or infinite system of discontinuous quasimonotone differential equations. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 128 (2000), 3349-3360. Abstract: This paper proves the existence of solutions to the initial value problem
x'(t)=f(t,x(t))  (0£t£1),      x(0)=0
where f : [0,1]´RM ® RM may be discontinuous but is assumed to satisfy conditions of superposition-measurability, quasimonotonicity, quasisemicontinuity, and integrability. The set M can be arbitrarily large (finite or infinite); our theorem is new even for card(M)=2. The proof is based partly on measure-theoretic techniques used in one dimension under slightly stronger hypotheses by Rzymowski and Walachowski. Further generalizations are mentioned at the end of the paper.
 
ANALYSIS
  Handbook of Analysis and its Foundations, published by Academic Press. (Hardback, 1996/1997; 883 + xxii pages long. The CD-ROM published in 1999 contained an additional chapter.) (This is not research, but an expository/reference work. That is, instead of new discoveries, it attempts to make more accessible to students some results that were already present in the literature.) The book's main themes are -- and indeed, its prepublication title was -- Choice, Compactness, Completeness; those are three main methods of proving the existence of a mathematical object. HAF explores how these arise in analysis and in fields closely connected with analysis. The exploration of the Axiom of Choice is based on a brief, intuitive discussion of constructivism, which S.I.A.M. Review called "the most satisfying reflection on constructivism I have ever seen"; in general that review called the book "daring and innovative." The book shows the connections underlying many different parts of mathematics that are usually presented separately. The book also explores the limitations of many basic principles of analysis -- for instance, every analyst knows Banach's Contraction Fixed Point Theorem, but few know the converses of Meyers and Bessaga, which show that in certain respects Banach's result cannot be improved. The book includes some of the "folklore" results -- i.e., basic ideas that are well known to advanced researchers but that graduate students sometimes have difficulty locating in the literature. S.I.A.M. Review said
    Every once in a while a book comes along that so effectively redefines an educational enterprise -- in this case, graduate mathematical training -- and so effectively reexamines the hegemony of ideas prevailing in a discipline -- in this case, mathematical analysis -- that it deserves our careful attention. This is such a book. There is nothing else remotely similar to it in any of the current books on integration, real analysis, set theory, or any other related subject. ...
The book is has a web page of its own which describes the book further and includes some brief excerpts -- e.g., charts and lists of about 100 forms of the Axiom of Choice and its consequences.
 
ALGEBRA
  Review of "Solving the Quintic", a poster by Wolfram Research. My review of Wolfram's poster was published in the Mathematical Intelligencer 17 (1995), 71-73. Review is suitable for beginners -- it includes an introduction to the problem of solving polynomial equations by formulas analogous to the quadratic formula.
 
SET
THEORY
  Two topological equivalents of the Axiom of Choice. Zeit. fur math. Logik und Grund. Math. 38 (1992), 555-557. We show that the Axiom of Choice is equivalent to each of the following statements: a product of closures of subsets of topological spaces is equal to the closure of their product (in the product topology); and a product of complete uniform spaces is complete.
 
DIFFERENTIAL
EQUATIONS
  A survey of local existence theories for abstract nonlinear initial value problems. Springer Lecture Notes in Math. 1394 (1989), 136-184. This paper surveys the abstract theories concerning local-in-time existence of solutions to differential inclusions, u'(t) in F(t,u(t)), in a Banach space. Three main approaches assume generalized compactness, isotonicity in an ordered Banach space, or dissipativeness. We consider different notions of "solution," and also the importance of assuming or not assuming that F(t,x) is continuous in x. Other topics include Caratheodory conditions, uniqueness, semigroups, semicontinuity, subtangential conditions, limit solutions, continuous dependence of u on F, and bijections between u and F. Reprint available in several formats.
 
DIFFERENTIAL
EQUATIONS
  Compact perturbations of linear m-dissipative operators which lack Gihman's property. Springer Lecture Notes in Math. 1248 (1987), 142-161. Some questions about abstract methods for initial value problems lead us to a study of the equation (*) u'(t) = (A+B)u(t), where A is m-dissipative and B is compact. Does a solution to (*) necessarily exist? Earlier studies of this question, reviewed and then continued here, depend on an analysis of the related quasiautonomous equation (**) u'(t) = Au(t)+f(t). We say A has Gihman's property if the mapping f |® u is continuous from L1w([0,T],K) into C([0,T];X) for every compact set K contained in X; this condition is closely related to the Lie-Trotter-Kato product formula. If A has this property, then (*) is known to have a solution. In this paper, we consider linear, m-dissipative operators A which lack Gihman's property. We obtain partial results regarding the existence of solutions of (*); but in general, the existence question remains open. Our method applies the variation of parameters formula to (**), but this requires a weakened topology when Range(f) is not contained in the closure of Domain(A). Two examples are studied: one in l¥, the other in the space of bounded continuous functions.